Saturday, March 29, 2008


The Courier & Advertiser, more commonly known as simply The Courier, is a broadsheet newspaper published by DC Thomson in Dundee, Scotland. It is printed in six daily editions: the Early edition, and regional editions for Fife, north-east Fife, Perth, Angus and Dundee.
Established in 1801 as the Dundee Courier & Argus, the entire front page of The Courier used to contain classified advertisements - a traditional newspaper format for many years. As one of the UK's biggest selling morning regional newspapers [1] with daily circulation of around 80,000 [2], The Courier was unusual in maintaining this format until 1992, when it adopted a conventional 'headline news' format.
The editorials, in particular, used to be noted for their brevity, with a separate paragraph for each short sentence and no long words - which probably made it one of the easiest to read, or most straightforward, of broadsheet newspapers.

The Courier See also

List of newspapers in Scotland

Friday, March 28, 2008


A workflow is a reliably repeatable pattern of activity enabled by a systematic organization of resources, defined roles and mass, energy and information flows, into a work process that can be documented and learned. Workflows are always designed to achieve processing intents of some sort, such as physical transformation, service provision, or information processing.
Workflows are closely related to other concepts used to describe organizational structure, such as silos, functions, teams, projects, policies and hierarchies. Workflows may be viewed as one primitive building block of organizations. The relationships among these concepts are described later in this entry.

Related concepts
Workflows are a distinctly modern phenomenon. While one might imagine individual efforts in rational organization of labor in the construction of historical artifacts such as the pyramids, the idea that one can create value by studying the nature of work itself and organizing it better is a distinctly modern one that should probably be attributed to Adam Smith. It is easiest to understand the development of the notions of workflow in terms of loosely defined eras, with a great deal of overlap.
Beginnings in Manufacturing (1900-1950): Notions of workflow are best understood in terms of the historical development of the conceptualization of work itself. The modern history of workflows can be traced to F. W. Taylor (Taylor, 1919) and H. Gantt. Together they launched the study of the deliberate, rational organization of work, in the context of manufacturing. The types of workflow of concern to Taylor and his contemporaries primarily involved mass and energy flows, and these were studied and improved using time and motion studies. Information-based workflows, however, did begin to grow in the same era. A particularly influential figure was Melvil Dewey who, besides inventing the eponymous Dewey Decimal System, was also responsible for the development of the hanging file folder. While the assembly line remains the most famous example of a workflow from this era, the early thinking around work was far more sophisticated than is commonly understood, and the notion of flow was more than a sequential breakdown of processing. The common conceptual models of modern operations research, including flow shops, job shops and queuing systems (Pinedo, 2001) can be found in evolved forms in early 20th century industry. That said, this early era was still limited by its relatively inflexible notions of information flow and thus is identified with the simplest notions of workflow optimization and productivity: throughput and resource utilization. The cultural impact of this era of workflows can be understood through films such as Chaplin's classic Modern Times. These concepts did not stay confined to the shop floor (one magazine invited housewives to puzzle over the fastest way to toast three slices of bread on a one-side, two-slice grill). The popular cheaper by the dozen introduced the emerging concepts to the context of family life.
Maturation and Growth (1950-1980): The invention of the typewriter and the copier allowed the principles of rational organization of labor, first discovered in the manufacturing shop floor. Paper, filing systems and sophisticated systems of managing physically manifest information flows evolved. Alongside this increasing scope of formalized workflows to information work, two other events provided a huge impetus for the development of thought around workflows. These were the development of mathematical optimization techniques and the maturation of the field of optimization and the impact of World War II and the Apollo program, both unprecedented in their demands for the rational organization of work. In cultural terms, the classic management tome, The Organization Man documented the nature of work in this era.
The Quality Era (1980-1995): By 1980 two glaring flaws in the nature of the supposedly scientific organization of workflows became apparent. The first was that the methods pioneered by Taylor only applied to humans conceptualized as one-dimensional automatons. Considered in the light of human needs for self-actualization, creative engagement in work and growth (the Maslow hierarchy became a popular tool in this critique), the classical industrial-style organization of work was critiqued as being both dehumanizing and suboptimal in its use of the potential of human beings. The second critique had to do with quality. Workflows conceptualized to be rational with respect at a given time, even with the best of intentions, were understood to acquire inertia and rigidity, rendering them irrational with respect to changing work conditions. The first critique did not gain much traction other than acknowledgement as an issue, but quality, in both analytic and synthetic manifestations, transformed the nature of work through a variety of movements ranging from total quality management to six sigma to more qualitative notions of business process re-engineering (Hammers and Champy, 1991). Under the influence of the quality movement, workflows became the subject of much scrutiny and optimization efforts. Acknowledgement of the dynamic and changing nature of the demands on workflows came in the form of recognition of the phenomena associated with critical paths and moving bottlenecks (Goldratt, E., 1996).
The Information Era (1990 - 2002): The experiences with the quality movement made it clear that information flows are fundamentally different from the mass and energy flows which inspired the first forms of rational workflows. The low cost and adaptability of information flows were seen as enabling workflows that were at once highly rational in their organization and highly flexible, adaptable and responsive. These insights unleashed a whole range of information technology at workflows in manufacturing, services and pure information work. Flexible manufacturing systems, just in time inventory management and other highly agile and adaptable systems of workflow are products of this era.
The Virtual Workflow Era (2002): The Internet bust of the early years of the 21st century led to a period of caution towards ambitious conceptualizations of smart workflows. Today, a variety of actors in the economy are returning to a consideration of the problem of developing models of work that are at once rational, flexible and capable of taking advantage of globalization, distributed work practices, while allowing the humans embedded in them to realize their full creative potential. Among the most exciting developments are the serious thought given to apparently anarchic systems of organization that have evolved in the open source software community.

Workflow Historical development
The following examples illustrate the variety of workflows seen in various contexts:

In military planning, a Concept of Operations (CONOPS) is a workflow that defines particular mission types
In machine shops, particularly job shops and flow shops, the flow of a part through the various processing stations is a work flow
Insurance claims processing is an example of an information-intensive, document-driven workflow
Wikipedia editing is an example of a stochastic workflow
The Getting Things Done (GTD) system is a model of personal workflow management for information workers Features and phenomenology
The key driver to gain benefit from the understanding of the workflow process in a business context is that the throughput of the workstream path is modelled in such a way as to evaluate the efficiency of the flow route through internal silos with a view to increasing discrete control of uniquely identified business attributes and rules and reducing potential low efficiency drivers. Evaluation of resources, both physical and human is essential to evaluate hand-off points and potential to create smoother transitions between tasks. Several workflow improvement theories have been proposed and implemented in the modern workplace. These include:
As a way of bridging the gap between the two, significant effort is being put into defining workflow patterns that can be used to compare and contrast different workflow engines across both of these domains.

Six Sigma
Total Quality Management
Business process reengineering
Lean systems Workflow improvement theories
A workflow can usually be described using formal or informal flow diagramming techniques, showing directed flows between processing steps. Single processing steps or components of a workflow can basically be defined by three parameters:
Components can only be plugged together if the output of one previous (set of) component(s) is equal to the mandatory input requirements of the following component. Thus, the essential description of a component actually comprises only in- and output that are described fully in terms of data types and their meaning (semantics). The algorithms' or rules' description need only be included when there are several alternative ways to transform one type of input into one type of output - possibly with different accuracy, speed, etc..
Especially when the components are non-local services that are invoked remotely via a computer network, like Web services, additional descriptors like QoS, availability, etc. have to be considered, too.

input description: the information, material and energy required to complete the step
transformation rules, algorithms, which may be carried out by associated human roles or machines, or a combination
output description: the information, material and energy produced by the step and provided as input to downstream steps. Workflow components
Main article: Workflow application
Many software systems to support workflows in particular domains exist. Such systems manage tasks such as automatic routing, partially automated processing and integration between different functional software applications and hardware systems that contribute to the value-addition process underlying the workflow.

See also

Thursday, March 27, 2008

Beta (letter)
Beta (uppercase Β, lowercase β and internal ϐ) is the second letter of the Greek alphabet. In the system of Greek numerals it has a value of 2. It was derived from the Phoenician letter Beth Beth. Letters that arose from Beta include the Roman B and the Cyrillic letters Б and В.
In Modern Greek, it represents a voiced labiodental fricative /v/, but in Ancient Greek, it represented a /b/.
Beta should not be confused with the German ligature eszett (ß), which closely resembles the lower case letter beta but is otherwise unrelated.
The Modern Greek name of the letter is [ˈviˑta]. The American pronunciation is [ˈbeɪɾə] whereas the British pronunciation is [ˈbiːtə]. See: American and British English pronunciation differences, IPA
In high-quality print, a variant of the letter is sometimes used that does not have a descender except at the beginning of a word: "βίβλος" is written "βίϐλος".

Wednesday, March 26, 2008

Background
MacMahon assembled the Ulster army in Loughgall in south Armagh, with 4000 infantry and 600 cavalry. They were, however short of ammunition and over half of their men carried pikes rather than muskets (whereas the norm at the time was one pike for two muskets). His aim was to march through the centre of Ulster and drive a wedge between Coote's garrison at Derry in the west of province and Venables' command at Carrickfergus in the east. With the Parliamentarian troops tied down by the activities of Irish guerrillas or "tories", the Ulster army marched up to Ballycastle on the northern coast of Ulster and left a string of garrisons along the centre of the province. They then marched west, towards Coote's army , which was in Lifford, near Derry. Fending off an attack by the English cavalry as they crossed the river Finn, the Irish encamped on a mountain side at Scarrifholis, south of Letterkenny along the road to Donegal town and near the river Swilly. The local Protestant population fled to the fortified towns in the area, as the war in Ulster had, from its outset, been characterised by atrocities committed against civilians by both sides. Meanwhile, Parliamentarian reinforcements had joined Coote from eastern Ulster, bringing his forces up to 3000 men, compared to 4000 Irish. However, the British force had more ammunition and more cavalry than their enemies. MacMahon's officers warned him not to leave their strong defensive position and risk battle, as the Parliamentary army was tactically superior to them. Rather, they should stay put and wait for the enemy to disperse when their supplies ran out, leaving the Irish free to march back to their stronghold along the border with Leinster. MacMahon however refused to listen to military advice and ordered his troops down from their mountain camp to give battle to the Parliamentary army.

Battle of Scarrifholis The battle
The battle was a decisive victory for Coote and British Parliamentarians. Over 3000 of the Ulster army were killed – 2000 on the field and another 1000 in the pursuit – about 75% of their total numbers. The Parliamentarians lost only around 100 soldiers killed. Coote ordered that Irish wounded and prisoners taken were to be killed, including Henry O'Neill, Owen Roe O'Neill's son, who had surrendered on terms. MacMahon was captured a week later at Enniskillen and hanged.
The battle marked the destruction of the Ulster army, not only because of the loss of manpower, which could be replaced, but because of the loss of many experienced officers and virtually all their weapons and equipment, which could not. In addition to O'Neill and MacMahon, the Irish lost 9 colonels, 4 lieutenant colonels, 3 majors, 20 captains and hundreds of other junior officers. This represented a huge cull of the Ulster Irish Catholic land-owning class, far bigger than in the famous Flight of the Earls in 1607. For this reason, the battle has been described as "Ulster's Aughrim" – a battle marking the extermination of the province's native aristocracy and assuring the continued existence and supremacy of its Protestant settler population.
Coote went on to march south, taking Sligo and then Galway after a long siege in 1652. The surrender of this city marked the effective end of the Irish resistance to the Cromwellian conquest of Ireland.

Tuesday, March 25, 2008


For the non-alcoholic beverage, see Freddie Bartholomew (cocktail)
Freddie Bartholomew (March 28, 1924January 23, 1992) was a British child actor, popular in 1930s Hollywood films.
Born Frederick Llewellyn March in Dublin, Ireland, Bartholomew was abandoned by his parents while a baby, and was raised in London by his aunt, whose name he took. While visiting the United States, Bartholomew was reportedly seen by film producer David O. Selznick who was soon to film Charles Dickens' David Copperfield (1935). Selznick had already cast American boy David Holt in the role, but after meeting Bartholomew realised that the character would benefit from being played by a British actor. The all-star film was a success and Bartholomew was cast in a succession of prestigious film productions with some of the most popular stars of the day.
Among his successes of the 1930s were Anna Karenina (1935), with Greta Garbo and Fredric March, Professional Soldier (1935) with Gloria Stuart, Little Lord Fauntleroy (1936) with Dolores Costello, Lloyds of London (1937) with Madeleine Carroll and Tyrone Power, and Captains Courageous (1937) with Spencer Tracy.
By this time Bartholomew's success and level of fame had caused his parents to attempt to gain custody of him. A protracted legal battle saw much of the wealth Bartholomew had amassed spent on legal fees. He continued acting into the 1940s but was much less popular as a teenaged actor, and by the early 1950s had retired from film.
He established a career in advertising and distanced himself from Hollywood. Bartholomew was said to have been bitter over his lost fortune and his experiences in Hollywood, but by the early 1980s he was working as a producer for the soap opera As The World Turns. Shortly before his death he allowed an interview for the television documentary MGM: When the Lion Roars (1992).
He died from emphysema in Sarasota, Florida.
Freddie Bartholomew has a star on the Hollywood Walk of Fame for his contribution to motion pictures, at 6667 Hollywood Boulevard.
Freddie Bartholomew

Monday, March 24, 2008


India has an extensive diplomatic network, reflecting its significant influence in the world and particuarly in the region in borders - Central Asia, the Middle East, East Africa, Southeast Asia and the Indian subcontinent. There are also far-flung missions in the Caribbean and the Pacific, locations of historical Indian diaspora communities.
As a Commonwealth country, India has High Commissions in the capitals of other member states. In other cities of Commonwealth countries India calls some of its consulates "Assistant High Commissions".

Europe

Canada

  • Ottawa (High Commission)
    Toronto (Consulate General)
    Vancouver (Consulate General)
    Cuba

    • Havana (Embassy)
      Jamaica

      • Kingston (High Commission)
        Mexico

        • Mexico City (Embassy)
          Panama

          • Panama City (Embassy)
            Trinidad and Tobago

            • Port of Spain (High Commission)
              United States

              • Washington DC (Embassy)
                Chicago (Consulate-General)
                Houston (Consulate-General)
                New York (Consulate-General)
                San Francisco (Consulate-General) North America

                Argentina

                • Buenos Aires (Embassy)
                  Brazil

                  • Brasília (Embassy)
                    São Paulo (Consulate-General)
                    Chile

                    • Santiago (Embassy)
                      Colombia

                      • Bogotá (Embassy)
                        Guyana

                        • Georgetown (High Commission)
                          Peru

                          • Lima (Embassy)
                            Suriname

                            • Paramaribo (Embassy)
                              Venezuela

                              • Caracas (Embassy) Indian diplomatic missions South America

                                Afghanistan

                                • Kabul (Embassy)
                                  Herat (Consulate-General)
                                  Jalalabad (Consulate-General)
                                  Khandahar (Consulate-General)
                                  Mazari Sharif (Consulate-General)
                                  Bangladesh

                                  • Dhaka (High Commission)
                                    Chittagong (Assistant High Commission)
                                    Rajshahi (Assistant High Commission)
                                    Bhutan

                                    • Thimphu (Embassy)
                                      Phuntsholing (Liaison Office)
                                      Brunei

                                      • Bandar Seri Begawan (High Commission)
                                        Cambodia

                                        • Phnom Penh (Embassy)
                                          China

                                          • Beijing (Embassy)
                                            Hong Kong (Consulate-General)
                                            Shanghai (Consulate-General)
                                            Indonesia

                                            • Jakarta (Embassy)
                                              Medan (Consulate-General)
                                              Japan

                                              • Tokyo (Embassy)
                                                Osaka (Consulate-General)
                                                Kazakhstan

                                                • Almaty (Embassy)
                                                  Korea, North

                                                  • Pyongyang (Embassy)
                                                    Korea, South

                                                    • Seoul (Embassy)
                                                      Kyrgyzstan

                                                      • Bishkek (Embassy)
                                                        Laos

                                                        • Vientiane (Embassy)
                                                          Malaysia

                                                          • Kuala Lumpur (High Commission)
                                                            Maldives

                                                            • Male (High Commission)
                                                              Mongolia

                                                              • Ulaanbaatar (Embassy)
                                                                Myanmar

                                                                • Yangon (Embassy)
                                                                  Mandalay (Consulate-General)
                                                                  Nepal

                                                                  • Kathmandu (Embassy)
                                                                    Birgunj (Consulate)
                                                                    Pakistan

                                                                    • Islamabad (High Commission)
                                                                      Karachi (Assistant High Commission)
                                                                      Philippines

                                                                      • Manila (Embassy)
                                                                        Singapore

                                                                        • Singapore (High Commission)
                                                                          Sri Lanka

                                                                          • Colombo (High Commission)
                                                                            Kandy (Assistant High Commission)
                                                                            Tajikistan

                                                                            • Dushanbe (Embassy)
                                                                              Thailand

                                                                              • Bangkok (Embassy)
                                                                                Chiang Mai (Consulate-General)
                                                                                Turkmenistan

                                                                                • Ashkabad (Embassy)
                                                                                  Uzbekistan

                                                                                  • Tashkent (Embassy)
                                                                                    Vietnam

                                                                                    • Hanoi (Embassy)
                                                                                      Ho Chi Minh City (Consulate-General) Middle East

                                                                                      Algeria

                                                                                      • Algiers (Embassy)
                                                                                        Angola

                                                                                        • Luanda (Embassy)
                                                                                          Botswana

                                                                                          • Gaborone (High Commission)
                                                                                            Burkina Faso

                                                                                            • Ouagadougou (Embassy)
                                                                                              Cote d'Ivoire

                                                                                              • Abidjan (Embassy)
                                                                                                Egypt

                                                                                                • Cairo (Embassy)
                                                                                                  Ethiopia

                                                                                                  • Addis Ababa (Embassy)
                                                                                                    Ghana

                                                                                                    • Accra (High Commission)
                                                                                                      Kenya

                                                                                                      • Nairobi (High Commission)
                                                                                                        Mombassa (Assistant High Commission)
                                                                                                        Libya

                                                                                                        • Tripoli (Embassy)
                                                                                                          Madagascar

                                                                                                          • Antananarivo (Embassy)
                                                                                                            Mauritius

                                                                                                            • Port Louis (High Commission)
                                                                                                              Morocco

                                                                                                              • Rabat (Embassy)
                                                                                                                Mozambique

                                                                                                                • Maputo (High Commission)
                                                                                                                  Namibia

                                                                                                                  • Windhoek (High Commission)
                                                                                                                    Nigeria

                                                                                                                    • Abuja (High Commission)
                                                                                                                      Lagos (Assistant High Commission)
                                                                                                                      Senegal

                                                                                                                      • Dakar (Embassy)
                                                                                                                        Seychelles

                                                                                                                        • Victoria, Seychelles (High Commission)
                                                                                                                          South Africa

                                                                                                                          • Pretoria (High Commission)
                                                                                                                            Cape Town (High Commission/Consulate-General)
                                                                                                                            Durban (Consulate-General)
                                                                                                                            Johannesburg (Consulate-General)
                                                                                                                            Sudan

                                                                                                                            • Khartoum (Embassy)
                                                                                                                              Tanzania

                                                                                                                              • Dar es Salam (High Commission)
                                                                                                                                Zanzibar (Consulate-General)
                                                                                                                                Tunisia

                                                                                                                                • Tunis (Embassy)
                                                                                                                                  Uganda

                                                                                                                                  • Kampala (High Commission)
                                                                                                                                    Zambia

                                                                                                                                    • Lusaka (High Commission)
                                                                                                                                      Zimbabwe

                                                                                                                                      • Harare (Embassy) Africa

                                                                                                                                        Australia

                                                                                                                                        • Canberra (High Commission)
                                                                                                                                          Sydney (Consulate-General)
                                                                                                                                          Fiji

                                                                                                                                          • Suva (High Commission)
                                                                                                                                            New Zealand

                                                                                                                                            • Wellington (High Commission)
                                                                                                                                              Papua New Guinea

                                                                                                                                              • Port Morseby (High Commission) Indian diplomatic missions Multilateral organisations

                                                                                                                                                India
                                                                                                                                                Foreign relations of India

Sunday, March 23, 2008


The Blue Jay (Cyanocitta cristata) is a passerine bird and member of the crow family Corvidae native to North America. It is adaptable, aggressive and omnivorous.

Blue Jay Distribution and habitat
The Blue Jay is generally aggressive toward other birds, and it will chase birds from feeders or other food sources. It may chase birds of prey, such as hawks and owls, which occasionally prey on jays, and will scream if it sees a predator within its territory. It may also be aggressive towards humans who come close to its nest, and if an owl roosts near the nest during the daytime, the Blue Jay attacks it until it takes a new roost. The Blue jay is a slow flier and an easy prey for hawks and owls, when it flies in open lands. It flies with body and tail held level, with slow wing beats.

Behavior
The voice is typical of most jays in being varied, but the most commonly recognized sound is the alarm call, which is a loud, almost gull-like scream. There is also a high-pitched jayer-jayer call that increases in speed as the bird becomes more agitated. Blue Jays will use these calls to band together to drive a predator such as a hawk away from their nest.
Blue Jays also have quiet, almost subliminal calls which they use among themselves in proximity. One of the most distinctive calls of this type is often referred to as the "rusty pump" owing to its squeaky resemblance to the sound of an old hand-operated water pump. In fact, they can make a large variety of sounds, and individuals may vary perceptibly in their calling style. Like other corvids, blue jays may learn to mimic human speech. [1]

Diet
The breeding season begins in mid-March, peaks in mid-April to May, and extends into July. Any suitable tree or large bush may be used for nesting, though an evergreen is preferred, and the nest is built at a height of 3 to 10 m.The adults build a cup-shaped nest of twigs, small roots, bark strips, moss, other plant material, cloth, paper, and feathers, with occasional mud added to the cup.

Saturday, March 22, 2008


Johannes Peter "Honus" Wagner (February 24, 1874 - December 6, 1955), nicknamed "The Flying Dutchman", was an American baseball player who played during the 1890s until the 1910s. In 1936, the Baseball Hall of Fame inducted Wagner as one of the first five members. Although Ty Cobb is frequently cited as the greatest player of the dead-ball era, some contemporaries regarded Wagner as the better all-around player, and most baseball historians consider Wagner to be the greatest shortstop ever. Cobb himself called Wagner "maybe the greatest star ever to take the diamond." (My Life in Baseball: The True Record, Ty Cobb and Al Stump, Doubleday, 1961, p.123)

Louisville Colonels (1897-1899)
Pittsburgh Pirates (1900-1917)
World Series Champion: 1909
National League Pennant: 1903, 1909
NL batting titles (x8)
NL RBI title (x5)
Led the NL in stolen bases (x4)
200-hit seasons (x2) Early life and Family
Wagner began his career with the Louisville Colonels in 1897, and by the next season was already one of the best hitters in the National League. After the 1899 season, the NL contracted from twelve to eight teams, and the Colonels were one of the teams eliminated. Many of the Colonels, including Wagner, were assigned to the Pittsburgh Pirates, and Wagner played the next 18 seasons for his hometown team.
Wagner helped the Pirates win NL pennants in 1901, 1902 and 1903. In 1903 the Pirates played the Boston Puritans (soon to be renamed the Boston Red Sox) in the first World Series, losing five games to three in a best-of-nine series to a team led by pitcher Cy Young and third baseman-manager Jimmy Collins. In 1909 Wagner led the Pirates to another pennant, and they defeated the Detroit Tigers, led by Ty Cobb, to win their first World Series.
Wagner was hailed as the best-fielding shortstop of his day, and spent significant time in the outfield as well. He would eventually play every position except catcher, even making two appearances as a pitcher.
He led the NL in batting average eight times (only Cobb and Tony Gwynn have led a league in batting that often), slugging percentage six times, on-base percentage four times, total bases six times, doubles seven times, triples three times runs batted in five times and stolen bases five times, despite being bow-legged to the point where a contemporary sportswriter described his running as "resembling the gambols of a caracoling elephant."
His batting average peaked at .381 in 1900, his runs batted in at 126 in 1901, and twice, despite playing his entire career in the pre-1920 "Dead Ball Era," he hit 10 home runs in a season. His career totals include a .327 lifetime batting average, 640 doubles, 722 stolen bases, and a career total of 3,415 hits, a major league record until it was surpassed by Cobb in the 1920s and a National League record until it was surpassed by Stan Musial in 1961. He was 2nd player (since MLB officially began in 1876) to reach 3000 hits, joining Cap Anson in the magic circle.
Wagner was the final out of the first World Series ever. He struck out.

Playing career
Wagner served as the Pirates' manager briefly in 1917, but resigned the position after only 5 games. He returned to the Pirates as a coach, most notably as a hitting instructor from 1933 to 1952. Arky Vaughan, Kiki Cuyler, Ralph Kiner and player/manager from 1934-1939, Pie Traynor, all future Hall of Famers were notable "pupils" of Wagner. During this time, he wore uniform number 14, but later changed it to his more famous 33, which was later retired for him. (His entire playing career was in the days before uniform numbers were worn.)
Wagner lived out the remainder of his life in Pittsburgh, where he was well-known as a friendly figure around town. He died on December 6, 1955 at the age of 81, and is buried at Jefferson Memorial Cemetery in the South Hills area of Pittsburgh.

Honus Wagner Honors
The T206 Honus Wagner card has long been the most famous baseball card in existence. Known as the "Holy Grail" and the "Mona Lisa of baseball cards", an example of this card was the first baseball card to be sold for over a million dollars. On August 3, 2007 an SGC 10 graded card offered by Mastro Auctions sold for $192,000 to Robert Klevens of Prestige Collectibles, LLC acting on behalf of a client from Japan.

See also

Friday, March 21, 2008

Asia and South Pacific Design Automation Conference
The Asia and South Pacific Design Automation Conference, or ASP-DAC is a yearly conference on the topic of electronic design automation. It is typically held in late January in the Far East, as the name implies. It is sponsored by the IEEE Circuits and Systems Society (IEEE CASS), the Association for Computing Machinery (ACM)'s Special Interest Group on Design Automation SIGDA, and the Institute of Electronics Engineers of Korea (IEEK).
ASP-DAC is a combination of a trade show and a technical conference.

Thursday, March 20, 2008

Transmitted programmes

FM- and TV-mast Olsztyn-Pieczewo FM-Radio Programmes

List of masts

Wednesday, March 19, 2008


This article is part of the series:Parliament of Malaysia Politics and government of Malaysia
The Parliament of Malaysia is the national legislature of Malaysia, based on the Westminster system of Parliament. It consists of the Dewan Rakyat (House of Representatives or literally "People's Hall") and the Dewan Negara (literally "Nation's Hall"; commonly referred to as the Senate). Members of the Dewan Rakyat are known as members of Parliament (MPs) while members of the Dewan Negara are called senators.
A general election is held every four or five years to elect representatives to the Dewan Rakyat; members of the Dewan Negara, like those of the House of Lords in the United Kingdom, are appointed. Members of Parliament are commonly referred to as MPs.
The Parliament assembles in the Malaysian Houses of Parliament, located in the national capital city of Kuala Lumpur.

Constitution
Social contract
Yang di-Pertuan Agong

  • Mizan Zainal Abidin
    Cabinet

    • Prime Minister

      • Abdullah Ahmad Badawi
        Deputy Prime Minister

        • Najib Tun Razak
          Parliament

          • Dewan Negara
            Dewan Rakyat
            Judiciary
            The Opposition
            Elections

            • Election Commission
              Political parties
              States
              Foreign relations Scope
              Parliament meets from Monday to Thursday when it is in session, as Friday is part of the weekend in certain states such as Kelantan.

              Procedure
              In theory, based on the Constitution of Malaysia, the government is accountable to Parliament. However, there has been substantial controversy over the independence of the Malaysian Parliament, with many viewing it simply as a rubber stamp, approving the executive branch's decisions. Constitutional scholar Shad Saleem Faruqi has calculated that 80% of all bills the government introduced from 1991 to 1995 were passed without a single amendment. According to him, another 15% were withdrawn due to pressure from non-governmental organisations (NGOs) or other countries, while only 5% were amended or otherwise altered by Parliament. Shad concludes that "the legislative process is basically an executive process, not a parliamentary process."

              Relationship with the government
              Theoretically, the executive branch of the government is held in check by the legislative and judiciary branches. Parliament largely exerts control on the government through question time, where MPs question members of the cabinet on government policy, and through Select Committees that are formed to look into a particular issue.
              Formally, Parliament exercises control over legislation and financial affairs. However, the legislature has been condemned as having a "tendency to confer wide powers on ministers to enact delegated legislation", and a substantial portion of the government's revenue is not under Parliament's purview; government-linked companies, such as Petronas, are generally not accountable to Parliament.

              Checks and balances
              In early October of 2005 the Minister in the Prime Minister's Department in charge of parliamentary affairs, Nazri Aziz, announced the formation of a Department of Parliament to oversee its day-to-day running. The leader of the Opposition, Lim Kit Siang, immediately announced a "Save Parliament" campaign to "ensure that Parliament does not become a victim in the second most serious assault on the doctrine of separation of powers in the 48-year history of the nation".

              Current composition

              Politics of Malaysia
              Malaysian Houses of Parliament

Tuesday, March 18, 2008

European People's Party–European Democrats
The European People's Party (Christian Democrats) and European Democrats is a group in the European Parliament. It comprises the European People's Party and the non-party subgroup European Democrats (not to be confused with the centrist European Democratic Party). The abbreviated name is EPP-ED Group.
The EPP-ED Group is a parliamentary faction of Christian democrat and conservative parliamentarians. Virtually all parties represented in the EPP-ED Group belong to the European People's Party (EPP), the first-ever transnational political party to be formed at European level. The remaining parliamentarians, namely the United Kingdom Conservative Party and the Czech Civic Democratic Party (ODS) form the European Democrats and sit as allied Members of the Group.
Previously called the 'EPP Group', the EPP-ED nomenclature was adopted in 1999 to accommodate the institutional reservations of the British Conservative Party. After the European Parliament elections in 1999, it became the largest faction with 233 of the 626 seats. After the elections of 2004 elections, it remained the largest party group with 268 of the 732 seats. Since the accession of Bulgaria and Romania to the EU in January 2007, it now has 277 of the 785 seats (35%).
The present chair of the EPP–ED Group is French Member of the European Parliament (MEP) Joseph Daul, who was elected to that post on 9 January 2007.
On 13 July 2006, David Cameron, the leader of the British Conservative Party, and Czech Prime Minister-designate Mirek Topolánek, leader of the Civic Democratic Party, announced that their parties will leave the EPP-ED Group and form the Movement for European Reform following the European Parliament elections in 2009. Nevertheless, this attempt has remained limited to these two parties and has been snubbed by all major EPP member-parties. Most analysts doubt that Mr Cameron will be able to surpass the threshold values of MEPs needed from at least six nations, which is required for formal recognition and receipt of funding by the European Parliament.

Chairmen

Political parties of the world
Members of the European Parliament 2004-2009

Monday, March 17, 2008


Philosophy of mathematics is the branch of philosophy that studies the philosophical assumptions, foundations, and implications of mathematics.
Recurrent themes include:


  • What are the sources of mathematical subject matter?

  • What is the ontological status of mathematical entities?

  • What does it mean to refer to a mathematical object?

  • What is the character of a mathematical proposition?

  • What is the relation between logic and mathematics?

  • What is the role of hermeneutics in mathematics?

  • What kinds of inquiry play a role in mathematics?

  • What are the objectives of mathematical inquiry?

  • What gives mathematics its hold on experience?

  • What are the human traits behind mathematics?

  • What is mathematical beauty?

  • What is the source and nature of mathematical truth?

  • What is the relationship between the abstract world of mathematics and the material universe?



The terms philosophy of mathematics and mathematical philosophy are frequently used as synonyms. The latter, however, may be used to mean at least three other things. One sense refers to a project of formalizing a philosophical subject matter, say, aesthetics, ethics, logic, metaphysics, or theology, in a purportedly more exact and rigorous form, as for example the labors of Scholastic theologians, or the systematic aims of Leibniz and Spinoza. Another sense refers to the working philosophy of an individual practitioner or a like-minded community of practicing mathematicians. Additionally, some understand the term mathematical philosophy to be an allusion to the approach taken by Bertrand Russell in his book Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy.

What are the sources of mathematical subject matter?
What is the ontological status of mathematical entities?
What does it mean to refer to a mathematical object?
What is the character of a mathematical proposition?
What is the relation between logic and mathematics?
What is the role of hermeneutics in mathematics?
What kinds of inquiry play a role in mathematics?
What are the objectives of mathematical inquiry?
What gives mathematics its hold on experience?
What are the human traits behind mathematics?
What is mathematical beauty?
What is the source and nature of mathematical truth?
What is the relationship between the abstract world of mathematics and the material universe? Historical overview
A perennial issue in the philosophy of mathematics concerns the relationship between logic and mathematics at their joint foundations. While 20th century philosophers continued to ask the questions mentioned at the outset of this article, the philosophy of mathematics in the 20th century was characterized by a predominant interest in formal logic, set theory, and foundational issues.
It is a profound puzzle that on the one hand mathematical truths seem to have a compelling inevitability, but on the other hand the source of their 'truthfullness' remains elusive. Investigations into this issue are known as the foundations of mathematics program.
At the start of the century, philosophers of mathematics were already beginning to divide into various schools of thought about all these questions, broadly distinguished by their pictures of mathematical epistemology and ontology. Three schools, formalism, intuitionism, and logicism, emerged at this time, partly in response to the increasingly widespread worry that mathematics as it stood, and analysis in particular, did not live up to the standards of certainty and rigor that had been taken for granted. Each school addressed the issues that came to the fore at that time, either attempting to resolve them or claiming that mathematics is not entitled to its status as our most trusted knowledge.
Surprising and counterintuitive developments in formal logic and set theory early in the 20th century led to new questions concerning what was traditionally called the foundations of mathematics. As the century unfolded, the initial focus of concern expanded to an open exploration of the fundamental axioms of mathematics, the axiomatic approach having been taken for granted since the time of Euclid as the natural basis for mathematics. Core concepts such as axiom, order, and set received fresh emphasis. In mathematics as in physics, new and unexpected ideas had arisen and significant changes were coming. Inquiries into the consistency of mathematical theories led to the development of a new level of study, a reflective critique in which the theory under review "becomes itself the object of a mathematical study", what Hilbert called metamathematics or proof theory (Kleene, 55).
At the midpoint of the century, a new mathematical theory known as category theory arose as a new contender for the natural language of mathematical thinking (Mac Lane 1998). As the 20th century progressed, however, philosophical opinions diverged as to just how well-founded were the questions about foundations that were raised at its opening. Hilary Putnam summed up one common view of the situation in the last third of the century by saying:
When philosophy discovers something wrong with science, sometimes science has to be changed — Russell's paradox comes to mind, as does Berkeley's attack on the actual infinitesimal — but more often it is philosophy that has to be changed. I do not think that the difficulties that philosophy finds with classical mathematics today are genuine difficulties; and I think that the philosophical interpretations of mathematics that we are being offered on every hand are wrong, and that 'philosophical interpretation' is just what mathematics doesn't need. (Putnam, 169–170).
Philosophy of mathematics today proceeds along several different lines of inquiry, by philosophers of mathematics, logicians, and mathematicians, and there are many schools of thought on the subject. The schools are addressed separately in the next section, and their assumptions explained.

Philosophy of mathematics in the 20th century

Contemporary schools of thought
Mathematical realism, like realism in general, holds that mathematical entities exist independently of the human mind. Thus humans do not invent mathematics, but rather discover it, and any other intelligent beings in the universe would presumably do the same. In this point of view, there is really one sort of mathematics that can be discovered: Triangles, for example, are real entities, not the creations of the human mind.
Many working mathematicians have been mathematical realists; they see themselves as discoverers of naturally occurring objects. Examples include Paul Erdős and Kurt Gödel. Gödel believed in an objective mathematical reality that could be perceived in a manner analogous to sense perception. Certain principles (e.g., for any two objects, there is a collection of objects consisting of precisely those two objects) could be directly seen to be true, but some conjectures, like the continuum hypothesis, might prove undecidable just on the basis of such principles. Gödel suggested that quasi-empirical methodology could be used to provide sufficient evidence to be able to reasonably assume such a conjecture.
Within realism, there are distinctions depending on what sort of existence one takes mathematical entities to have, and how we know about them.

Mathematical realism
Platonism is the form of realism that suggests that mathematical entities are abstract, have no spatiotemporal or causal properties, and are eternal and unchanging. This is often claimed to be the naive view most people have of numbers. The term Platonism is used because such a view is seen to parallel Plato's belief in a "World of Ideas", an unchanging ultimate reality that the everyday world can only imperfectly approximate. The two ideas have a meaningful, not just a superficial connection, because Plato probably derived his understanding from the Pythagoreans of ancient Greece, who believed that the world was, quite literally, generated by numbers.
The major problem of mathematical platonism is this: precisely where and how do the mathematical entities exist, and how do we know about them? Is there a world, completely separate from our physical one, which is occupied by the mathematical entities? How can we gain access to this separate world and discover truths about the entities? One answer might be Ultimate ensemble, which is a theory that postulates all structures that exist mathematically also exist physically in their own universe.
Gödel's platonism postulates a special kind of mathematical intuition that lets us perceive mathematical objects directly. (This view bears resemblances to many things Husserl said about mathematics, and supports Kant's idea that mathematics is synthetic a priori.) Davis and Hersh have suggested in their book The Mathematical Experience that most mathematicians act as though they are Platonists, even though, if pressed to defend the position carefully, they may retreat to formalism (see below).
Some mathematicians hold opinions that amount to more nuanced versions of Platonism. These ideas are sometimes described as Neo-Platonism.

Platonism
Logicism is the thesis that mathematics is reducible to logic, and hence nothing but a part of logic (Carnap 1931/1883, 41). Logicists hold that mathematics can be known a priori, but suggest that our knowledge of mathematics is just part of our knowledge of logic in general, and is thus analytic, not requiring any special faculty of mathematical intuition. In this view, logic is the proper foundation of mathematics, and all mathematical statements are necessary logical truths.
Rudolf Carnap (1931) presents the logicist thesis in two parts:










1. The concepts of mathematics can be derived from logical concepts through explicit definitions.
2. The theorems of mathematics can be derived from logical axioms through purely logical deduction.


Gottlob Frege was the founder of logicism. In his seminal Die Grundgesetze der Arithmetik (Basic Laws of Arithmetic) he built up arithmetic from a system of logic with a general principle of comprehension, which he called "Basic Law V" (for concepts F and G, the extension of F equals the extension of G if and only if for all objects a, Fa if and only if Ga), a principle that he took to be acceptable as part of logic.
But Frege's construction was flawed. Russell discovered that Basic Law V is inconsistent (this is Russell's paradox). Frege abandoned his logicist program soon after this, but it was continued by Russell and Whitehead. They attributed the paradox to "vicious circularity" and built up what they called ramified type theory to deal with it. In this system, they were eventually able to build up much of modern mathematics but in an altered, and excessively complex, form (for example, there were different natural numbers in each type, and there were infinitely many types). They also had to make several compromises in order to develop so much of mathematics, such as an "axiom of reducibility". Even Russell said that this axiom did not really belong to logic.
Modern logicists (like Bob Hale, Crispin Wright, and perhaps others) have returned to a program closer to Frege's. They have abandoned Basic Law V in favour of abstraction principles such as Hume's principle (the number of objects falling under the concept F equals the number of objects falling under the concept G if and only if the extension of F and the extension of G can be put into one-to-one correspondence). Frege required Basic Law V to be able to give an explicit definition of the numbers, but all the properties of numbers can be derived from Hume's principle. This would not have been enough for Frege because (to paraphrase him) it does not exclude the possibility that the number 3 is in fact Julius Caesar. In addition, many of the weakened principles that they have had to adopt to replace Basic Law V no longer seem so obviously analytic, and thus purely logical.
If mathematics is a part of logic, then questions about mathematical objects reduce to questions about logical objects. But what, one might ask, are the objects of logical concepts? In this sense, logicism can be seen as shifting questions about the philosophy of mathematics to questions about logic without fully answering them.

Logicism
Empiricism is a form of realism that denies that mathematics can be known a priori at all. It says that we discover mathematical facts by empirical research, just like facts in any of the other sciences. It is not one of the classical three positions advocated in the early 20th century, but primarily arose in the middle of the century. However, an important early proponent of a view like this was John Stuart Mill. Mill's view was widely criticized, because it makes statements like "2 + 2 = 4" come out as uncertain, contingent truths, which we can only learn by observing instances of two pairs coming together and forming a quartet.
Contemporary mathematical empiricism, formulated by Quine and Putnam, is primarily supported by the indispensability argument: mathematics is indispensable to all empirical sciences, and if we want to believe in the reality of the phenomena described by the sciences, we ought also believe in the reality of those entities required for this description. That is, since physics needs to talk about electrons to say why light bulbs behave as they do, then electrons must exist. Since physics needs to talk about numbers in offering any of its explanations, then numbers must exist. In keeping with Quine and Putnam's overall philosophies, this is a naturalistic argument. It argues for the existence of mathematical entities as the best explanation for experience, thus stripping mathematics of some of its distinctness from the other sciences.
Putnam strongly rejected the term "Platonist" as implying an overly-specific ontology that was not necessary to mathematical practice in any real sense. He advocated a form of "pure realism" that rejected mystical notions of truth and accepted much quasi-empiricism in mathematics. Putnam was involved in coining the term "pure realism" (see below).
The most important criticism of empirical views of mathematics is approximately the same as that raised against Mill. If mathematics is just as empirical as the other sciences, then this suggests that its results are just as fallible as theirs, and just as contingent. In Mill's case the empirical justification comes directly, while in Quine's case it comes indirectly, through the coherence of our scientific theory as a whole. Quine suggests that mathematics seems completely certain because the role it plays in our web of belief is incredibly central, and that it would be extremely difficult for us to revise it, though not impossible.
For a philosophy of mathematics that attempts to overcome some of the shortcomings of Quine and Gödel's approaches by taking aspects of each see Penelope Maddy's Realism in Mathematics. Another example of a realist theory is the embodied mind theory (see below).
For experimental evidence suggesting that one-day-old babies can do elementary arithmetic, see Brian Butterworth.

Empiricism
Formalism holds that mathematical statements may be thought of as statements about the consequences of certain string manipulation rules. For example, in the "game" of Euclidean geometry (which is seen as consisting of some strings called "axioms", and some "rules of inference" to generate new strings from given ones), one can prove that the Pythagorean theorem holds (that is, you can generate the string corresponding to the Pythagorean theorem). Mathematical truths are not about numbers and sets and triangles and the like — in fact, they aren't "about" anything at all!
Another version of formalism is often known as deductivism. In deductivism, the Pythagorean theorem is not an absolute truth, but a relative one: if you assign meaning to the strings in such a way that the rules of the game become true (ie, true statements are assigned to the axioms and the rules of inference are truth-preserving), then you have to accept the theorem, or, rather, the interpretation you have given it must be a true statement. The same is held to be true for all other mathematical statements. Thus, formalism need not mean that mathematics is nothing more than a meaningless symbolic game. It is usually hoped that there exists some interpretation in which the rules of the game hold. (Compare this position to structuralism.) But it does allow the working mathematician to continue in his or her work and leave such problems to the philosopher or scientist. Many formalists would say that in practice, the axiom systems to be studied will be suggested by the demands of science or other areas of mathematics.
A major early proponent of formalism was David Hilbert, whose program was intended to be a complete and consistent axiomatization of all of mathematics. ("Consistent" here means that no contradictions can be derived from the system.) Hilbert aimed to show the consistency of mathematical systems from the assumption that the "finitary arithmetic" (a subsystem of the usual arithmetic of the positive integers, chosen to be philosophically uncontroversial) was consistent. Hilbert's goals of creating a system of mathematics that is both complete and consistent was dealt a fatal blow by the second of Gödel's incompleteness theorems, which states that sufficiently expressive consistent axiom systems can never prove their own consistency. Since any such axiom system would contain the finitary arithmetic as a subsystem, Gödel's theorem implied that it would be impossible to prove the system's consistency relative to that (since it would then prove its own consistency, which Gödel had shown was impossible). Thus, in order to show that any axiomatic system of mathematics is in fact consistent, one needs to first assume the consistency of a system of mathematics that is in a sense stronger than the system to be proven consistent.
Hilbert was initially a deductivist, but, as may be clear from above, he considered certain metamathematical methods to yield intrinsically meaningful results and was a realist with respect to the finitary arithmetic. Later, he held the opinion that there was no other meaningful mathematics whatsoever, regardless of interpretation.
Other formalists, such as Rudolf Carnap, Alfred Tarski and Haskell Curry, considered mathematics to be the investigation of formal axiom systems. Mathematical logicians study formal systems but are just as often realists as they are formalists.
Formalists are usually very tolerant and inviting to new approaches to logic, non-standard number systems, new set theories etc. The more games we study, the better. However, in all three of these examples, motivation is drawn from existing mathematical or philosophical concerns. The "games" are usually not arbitrary.
The main critique of formalism is that the actual mathematical ideas that occupy mathematicians are far removed from the minute string manipulation games mentioned above. While published proofs (if correct) could in principle be formulated in terms of these games, the effort required in space and time would be prohibitive (witness Principia Mathematica.) In addition, the rules are certainly not substantial to the initial creation of those proofs. Formalism is also silent to the question of which axiom systems ought to be studied.

Formalism

Main article: Mathematical intuitionism Intuitionism

Main article: Mathematical constructivism Constructivism
Fictionalism was introduced in 1980 when Hartry Field published Science Without Numbers, which rejected and in fact reversed Quine's indispensability argument. Where Quine suggested that mathematics was indispensable for our best scientific theories, and therefore should be accepted as a body of truths talking about independently existing entities, Field suggested that mathematics was dispensable, and therefore should be considered as a body of falsehoods not talking about anything real. He did this by giving a complete axiomatization of Newtonian mechanics that didn't reference numbers or functions at all. He started with the "betweenness" of Hilbert's axioms to characterize space without coordinatizing it, and then added extra relations between points to do the work formerly done by vector fields. Hilbert's geometry is mathematical, because it talks about abstract points, but in Field's theory, these points are the concrete points of physical space, so no special mathematical objects at all are needed.
Having shown how to do science without using mathematics, he proceeded to rehabilitate mathematics as a kind of useful fiction. He showed that mathematical physics is a conservative extension of his non-mathematical physics (that is, every physical fact provable in mathematical physics is already provable from his system), so that the mathematics is a reliable process whose physical applications are all true, even though its own statements are false. Thus, when doing mathematics, we can see ourselves as telling a sort of story, talking as if numbers existed. For Field, a statement like "2 + 2 = 4" is just as false as "Sherlock Holmes lived at 221B Baker Street" — but both are true according to the relevant fictions.
By this account, there are no metaphysical or epistemological problems special to mathematics. The only worries left are the general worries about non-mathematical physics, and about fiction in general. Field's approach has been very influential, but is widely rejected. This is in part because of the requirement of strong fragments of second-order logic to carry out his reduction, and because the statement of conservativity seems to require quantification over abstract models or deductions. Another objection is that it is not clear how one could have certain results in science, such as quantum theory or the periodic table, without mathematics. If what distinguishes one element from another is *precisely* the number of electrons, neutrons and protons, how does one distinguish between elements without a concept of number?

Fictionalism
Embodied mind theories hold that mathematical thought is a natural outgrowth of the human cognitive apparatus which finds itself in our physical universe. For example, the abstract concept of number springs from the experience of counting discrete objects. It is held that mathematics is not universal and does not exist in any real sense, other than in human brains. Humans construct, but do not discover, mathematics.
With this view, the physical universe can thus be seen as the ultimate foundation of mathematics: it guided the evolution of the brain and later determined which questions this brain would find worthy of investigation. However, the human mind has no special claim on reality or approaches to it built out of math. If such constructs as Euler's identity are true then they are true as a map of the human mind and cognition.
Embodied mind theorists thus explain the effectiveness of mathematics — mathematics was constructed by the brain in order to be effective in this universe.
The most accessible, famous, and infamous treatment of this perspective is Where Mathematics Comes From, by George Lakoff and Rafael E. Núñez. In addition, mathematician Keith Devlin has investigated similar concepts with his book The Math Instinct. For more on the science that inspired this perspective, see cognitive science of mathematics.

Embodied mind theories
Social constructivism or social realism theories see mathematics primarily as a social construct, as a product of culture, subject to correction and change. Like the other sciences, mathematics is viewed as an empirical endeavor whose results are constantly evaluated and may be discarded. However, while on an empiricist view the evaluation is some sort of comparison with 'reality', social constructivists emphasize that the direction of mathematical research is dictated by the fashions of the social group performing it or by the needs of the society financing it. However, although such external forces may change the direction of some mathematical research, there are strong internal constraints- the mathematical traditions, methods, problems, meanings and values into which mathematicians are enculturated- that work to conserve the historically defined discipline.
This runs counter to the traditional beliefs of working mathematicians, that mathematics is somehow pure or objective. But social constructivists argue that mathematics is in fact grounded by much uncertainty: as mathematical practice evolves, the status of previous mathematics is cast into doubt, and is corrected to the degree it is required or desired by the current mathematical community. This can be seen in the development of analysis from reexamination of the calculus of Leibniz and Newton. They argue further that finished mathematics is often accorded too much status, and folk mathematics not enough, due to an over-emphasis on axiomatic proof and peer review as practices. However, this might be seen as merely saying that rigorously proven results are overemphasized, and then "look how chaotic and uncertain the rest of it all is!"
The social nature of mathematics is highlighted in its subcultures. Major discoveries can be made in one branch of mathematics and be relevant to another, yet the relationship goes undiscovered for lack of social contact between mathematicians. Social constructivists argue each speciality forms its own epistemic community and often has great difficulty communicating, or motivating the investigation of unifying conjectures that might relate different areas of mathematics. Social constructivists see the process of 'doing mathematics' as actually creating the meaning, while social realists see a deficiency either of human capacity to abstractify, or of human's cognitive bias, or of mathematicians' collective intelligence as preventing the comprehension of a real universe of mathematical objects. Social constructivists sometimes reject the search for foundations of mathematics as bound to fail, as pointless or even meaningless. Some social scientists also argue that mathematics is not real or objective at all, but is affected by racism and ethnocentrism. Some of these ideas are close to postmodernism.
Contributions to this school have been made by Imre Lakatos and Thomas Tymoczko, although it is not clear that either would endorse the title. More recently Paul Ernest has explicitly formulated a social constructivist philosophy of mathematics. [1] Some consider the work of Paul Erdős as a whole to have advanced this view (although he personally rejected it) because of his uniquely broad collaborations, which prompted others to see and study "mathematics as a social activity", e.g. via the Erdős number. Reuben Hersh has also promoted the social view of mathematics, calling it a 'humanistic' approach [2], similar to but not quite the same as that associated with Alvin White [3]; one of Hersh's co-authors, Philip J. Davis, has expressed sympathy for the social view as well.
A criticism of this approach is that it is trivial, based on the trivial observation that mathematics is a human activity. To observe that rigorous proof comes only after unrigorous conjecture, experimentation and speculation is true, but it is trivial and noone would deny this. So it's a bit of a stretch to characterize a philosophy of mathematics in this way, on something trivially true. The calculus of Leibniz and Newton was reexamined by mathematicians such as Weierstrauss in order to rigorously prove the theorems thereof. There is nothing special or interesting about this, as it fits in with the more general trend of unrigorous ideas which are later made rigorous. There needs to be a clear distinction between the objects of study of mathematics and the study of the objects of study of mathematics. The former doesn't seem to change a great deal; the latter is forever in flux. The latter is what the Social theory is about, and the former is what Platonism et al. are about.

Social constructivism or social realism
Rather than focus on narrow debates about the true nature of mathematical truth, or even on practices unique to mathematicians such as the proof, a growing movement from the 1960s to the 1990s began to question the idea of seeking foundations or finding any one right answer to why mathematics works. The starting point for this was Eugene Wigner's famous 1960 paper The Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics in the Natural Sciences, in which he argued that the happy coincidence of mathematics and physics being so well matched seemed to be unreasonable and hard to explain.
The embodied-mind or cognitive school and the social school were responses to this challenge, but the debates raised were difficult to confine to those.

Beyond the traditional schools
One parallel concern that does not actually challenge the schools directly but instead questions their focus is the notion of quasi-empiricism in mathematics. This grew from the increasingly popular assertion in the late 20th century that no one foundation of mathematics could be ever proven to exist. It is also sometimes called 'postmodernism in mathematics' although that term is considered overloaded by some and insulting by others. Quasi-empiricism argues that in doing their research, mathematicians test hypotheses as well as proving theorems. A mathematical argument can transmit falsity from the conclusion to the premises just as well as it can transmit truth from the premises to the conclusion. Quasi-empiricism was developed by Imre Lakatos, inspired by the philosophy of science of Karl Popper.
Lakatos's philosophy of mathematics is sometimes regarded as a kind of social constructivism, but this was not his intention.
Such methods have always been part of folk mathematics by which great feats of calculation and measurement are sometimes achieved. Indeed, such methods may be the only notion of proof a culture has.
Hilary Putnam has argued that any theory of mathematical realism would include quasi-empirical methods. He proposed that an alien species doing mathematics might well rely on quasi-empirical methods primarily, being willing often to forgo rigorous and axiomatic proofs, and still be doing mathematics - at perhaps a somewhat greater risk of failure of their calculations. He gave a detailed argument for this in New Directions (ed. Tymockzo, 1998).

Philosophy of mathematics Quasi-empiricism
Some practitioners and scholars who are not engaged primarily in proof-oriented approaches have suggested an interesting and important theory about the nature of mathematics. For example, Judea Pearl claimed that all of mathematics as presently understood was based on an algebra of seeing - and proposed an algebra of doing to complement it - this is a central concern of the philosophy of action and other studies of how knowledge relates to action. The most important output of this was new theories of truth, notably those appropriate to activism and grounding empirical methods.

Action
Few philosophers are able to penetrate mathematical notations and culture to relate conventional notions of metaphysics to the more specialized metaphysical notions of the schools above. This may lead to a disconnection in which some mathematicians continue to profess discredited philosophy as a justification for their continued belief in a world-view promoting their work.
Although the social theories and quasi-empiricism, and especially the embodied mind theory, have focused more attention on the epistemology implied by current mathematical practices, they fall far short of actually relating this to ordinary human perception and everyday understandings of knowledge.

Philosophy of mathematics Unification
Innovations in the philosophy of language during the 20th century renewed interest in the question as to whether mathematics is, as if often said, the language of science. Although most mathematicians and physicists (and many philosophers) would accept the statement "mathematics is a language", linguists believe that the implications of such a statement must be considered. For example, the tools of linguistics are not generally applied to the symbol systems of mathematics, that is, mathematics is studied in a markedly different way than other languages. If mathematics is a language, it is a different type of language than natural languages. Indeed, because of the need for clarity and specificity, the language of mathematics is far more constrained than natural languages studied by linguists. However, the methods developed by Gottlob Frege and Alfred Tarski for the study of mathematical language have been extended greatly by Tarski's student Richard Montague and other linguists working in formal semantics to show that the distinction between mathematical language and natural language may not be as great as it seems.
See also philosophy of language.

Language
Many practising mathematicians have been drawn to their subject because of a sense of beauty they perceive in it. One sometimes hears the sentiment that mathematicians would like to leave philosophy to the philosophers and get back to mathematics- where, presumably, the beauty lies.
In his work on the divine proportion, H. E. Huntley relates the feeling of reading and understanding someone else's proof of a theorem of mathematics to that of a viewer of a masterpiece of art - the reader of a proof has a similar sense of exhilaration at understanding as the original author of the proof, much as, he argues, the viewer of a masterpiece has a sense of exhilaration similar to the original painter or sculptor. Indeed, one can study mathematical and scientific writings as literature.
Philip Davis and Reuben Hersh have commented that the sense of mathematical beauty is universal amongst practicing mathematicians. By way of example, they provide two proofs of the irrationality of the √2. The first is the traditional proof by contradiction, ascribed to Euclid; the second is a more direct proof involving the fundamental theorem of arithmetic that, they argue, gets to the heart of the issue. Davis and Hersh argue that mathematicians find the second proof more aesthetically appealing because it gets closer to the nature of the problem.
Paul Erdős was well-known for his notion of a hypothetical "Book" containing the most elegant or beautiful mathematical proofs. There is not universal agreement that a result has one "most elegant" proof; Gregory Chaitin has argued against this idea.
Philosophers have sometimes criticized mathematicians' sense of beauty or elegance as being, at best, vaguely stated. By the same token, however, philosophers of mathematics have sought to characterize what makes one proof more desirable than another when both are logically sound.
Another aspect of aesthetics concerning mathematics is mathematicians' views towards the possible uses of mathematics for purposes deemed unethical or inappropriate. The best-known exposition of this view occurs in G.H. Hardy's book A Mathematician's Apology, in which Hardy argues that pure mathematics is superior in beauty to applied mathematics precisely because it cannot be used for war and similar ends. Some later mathematicians have characterized Hardy's views as mildly dated

Aesthetics

See also

Axiomatic set theory
Axiomatic system
Category theory
Formal language
Formal system
Foundations of mathematics
Golden ratio
History of mathematics
Intuitionistic logic
Logic
Mathematical beauty
Mathematical constructivism
Mathematical logic
Mathematical proof
Metamathematics
Model theory
Naive set theory
Non-standard analysis
Philosophy of language
Philosophy of science
Philosophy of probability
Proof theory
Rule of inference
Science studies
Scientific method
Set theory
Truth
The Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics in the Natural Sciences Related topics

The Analyst
Euclid's Elements
Gödel's completeness theorem
Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy
Kaina Stoicheia
New Foundations
Principia Mathematica
The Simplest Mathematics Related works

History and philosophy of science
History of mathematics
History of philosophy